Monday, February 28, 2011

why do we give wrong answers?

often times wrong answers to a given question arise from two reasons:

(a) the answerer is trying too hard, making a simple case way more complicated than it truly is

("missing the wood for the trees")

(b) the answerer is not trying at all

>95% of "research", "policy suggestions", "white papers", "discussion papers" etc falls into one of the above two.

keep in mind the inconsistent nature of this post, which follows (almost) by definition.

the path to be followed would be to simplify to the maximum extent possible.

Friday, February 18, 2011

"the market and the firm are placed on equal footing" (Williamson 2010)

galloping growth and hunger

this is quite a scandal, if the new york times is right. (by the by, why am I reading about this in the new york times?) is it really that laws prohibit corporations from owning large farms?

if that is right, my own unsubstantiated, knee-jerk view is that this is typical suspicion of the big ugly capitalist enterprise - this is justified to some extent but institution economics will say that different forms of organization are optimal under different conditions, optimal in the sense of producing at lesser cost.

no one wants food to become what it has in the US - mass produced flavour deficient product - but if I am to choose between this and malnutrition of the future of the country, which is the lesser evil is obvious.

Thursday, February 17, 2011

research statement

I write these words
great leaps of theory
all these thoughts that go unheard
from men greater than you or me

theory is metaphor and thus
this leaves me
free from worry

because I can choose my metaphor
and the idea now has a part of me
so I speak freely
telling people how I wish we could all be

good metaphor is hard, bad are easy
and, after all, greatness is subject to relativity

Monday, February 7, 2011

inversion

one day there will be a blog which will have a fresh post every day, detailing some little conundrum, or figuring out something paradoxical, or examining an old worn out subject with a brilliantly illuminating alternate view, a blog that will drip insight into your little sponge of a brain at the rate of one per day. this blog will be the ultimate blog, stirring passionate debate with every view, even the fence will be tempted to join in, thus calling into the question the whole notion of point and counterpoint. it will be evolutionarily revolutionary, and everyone will become smarter.

conversation at dinner parties will suddenly start to plumb the deepest of questions. conversations will start happening at after dinner parties. an eco-politico-socio-enviro-anthro-phsyic-historical perspective on everything will arise. there will then, one day, be no issue too great to solve. adam sandler will direct a 4 hour psycho thriller where a rudimentary understanding of string theory will be the least cognitive demand on the highly enlightened viewer. sarah palin will debate courageously with noam chomsky and amartya sen on the meaning of identity and freedom.

and then, alas, the blog will die, the most creative destruction ever known, for equilibrium is attained and the absolute truth has been discovered. mankind will plunge into darkness, and even the slightest flicker of light will seem like the radiance of a thousand suns, and the cycle will repeat...

Sunday, February 6, 2011

do you regard others in order to regard yourself?

"why have other regarding preferences?"

(a) "to protect the self from possible rent seeking we must understand the actions of the other"

(b) "this is evolutionarily sustainable strategy to preserve the species"

which answer grabs you? Are (a) and (b) independent of each other? What implicit assumptions underlie this question?

Thursday, February 3, 2011

What is an economic model?

In recent years, much has been written about behavioral biases in the actions of people, biases that contradict (apparently) the "rational choice" model in economics.

At first sight, such apparent irrationalities appear as a comforting thought ("surely people are not calculating utility at every instant!"). The more I've thought about it though, the less I am convinced that such irrationalities constitute a contradiction - a more appropriate term would be behavioral biases, as I've used in the first sentence.

To understand this, it is useful to begin here. It becomes apparent from reading that piece that one of the main motivations to introduce a utility function (probably first by Pareto then rigorously defined by Samuelson, if I get the paper) was to avoid such considerations of individual behavior.

A supposed irrational deviation from a supposed rational model can be criticized as follows - "the rational model is saying that people do what pleases them. Proving this mathematically requires some slightly strong axioms. So, one can see whether these axioms hold in the real world. Let's say you find they don't hold. Is it then fair to claim that the results do not follow through?"

Let me take an example. Imagine a lab experiment that demonstrates one group of people are unwilling to give up a coffee cup for a chocolate bar when they are "endowed" with a coffee cup, while the exact opposite holds for another group "endowed" with a chocolate bar. This is the endowment effect, and it is claimed to be irrational. One can argue however, that such endowment effects point to the fact that the basic preference ordering of any person is affected by what you give them. From here, lets say you derive a particular utility function that predicts exactly the supposed irrational behavior. Will you then say the behavior is irrational?

The criticism from the other side will then be - "okay, but you, rational choice theorist, claimed that preference orderings are fixed and unchanging, and now you alter that assumption. It is not surprising that you then get a different prediction." My reply would then be - "Precisely!"

This points to a basic fact about what a theory model in economics is, a fact that is becoming clearer to me over time. Theory in economics is never to be interpreted literally, it is highly metaphorical, yet mathematically exact. It is a way of thinking, a way to organize thoughts. Getting too deeply into how people make decisions - whether in the lab or field - is going to throw up so many different interpretations that it is going to be hard to make sense of them. Instead of claiming the rational choice model is wrong, I am quite sure that if people took the trouble of understanding exactly what extra dimension they are bringing in, a dimension that was not part of the traditional analysis, and how that affects the traditional analysis, we will all be better off.

Let me take another example. Think of the classic prisoner's dilemma problem - 2 person game. Now, we have a Nash equilibrium outcome (in pure strategies) which is inefficient in the sense that each is worse off than they could be, and another outcome which is efficient in the sense that each is as well off as possible. If you interpret this model literally, you will say "if I give people such payoffs I should never see anyone cooperating". Then you test this in a laboratory and find that actually people do cooperate. And you publish in the American Economic Review, claiming that "people don't play Nash thus they cannot be rational as defined".

My reply is twofold - (a) the utility function has been misdefined and (b) you're missing the point. Take (b) first. The point is not that people will play Nash or not, the point is much vaguer perhaps but more true, and it is this - "Adam Smith told us (by the way, the rest of this argument does great disservice to Smith who had a much more humane view of the world) the invisible hand (what a great metaphor!) of self interest makes everyone better off. Well this may not be true. Self interest alone may make everyone worse off." This, I don't think, anyone can have a problem with. After all think about any country, company, individual who "did well" - self interest played a big role perhaps in this, but surely it wasn't the only thing; we typically rely on many others often selfless contribution.

Point (a) is somewhat harder. If people are not playing Nash despite the (monetary) payoff indicating - as described by theory - that they should, the conclusion arguably is that there exist non-monetary payoffs that are driving the decisions being made. Thus the mapping from the utility function imagined by the authors of the published article to the monetary payoffs received isn't clear. Now, you may object - "yes, but you're just evading the issue by bringing up another cause that we cannot know is operating". My answer is - "Precisely". This is what we were trying to avoid when we said you get utility from what you consume, whatever that may be.

Of course, if neuroeconomics develops enough, we can actually understand (maybe) the mapping from utility to monetary as well as non-monetary payoffs. That may lay all this debate to rest.

But the broader point will remain - a theory in economics is not something where it is straightforward to take predictions to data. How a theory will operate in any circumstance must be understood not by the blackboard model offered by the theorist, but by understanding the broad meaning behind the mathematics, and interpreting that to analyze any situation. This isn't easy, and I believe requires just as much work as coming with the theory in the first place.

In fact, if you think about it, the idea that "people ought to work together to understand how a new observation can fit received theory, does it really contradict the theory or is the theory not supposed to apply there, etc" is just another way of stating that if we work together, we will be better off. Which is the lesson of the prisoner's dilemma.